The right to withdraw from controlled human infection studies: Justifications and avoidance

The right to withdraw from research without penalty is well established around the world. However, it has been challenged in some corners of bioethics based on concerns about various harms—to participants, to scientific integrity, and to research bystanders—that may stem from withdrawal. These conce...

Full description

Saved in:
Bibliographic Details
Published inBioethics Vol. 34; no. 8; pp. 833 - 848
Main Author Fernandez Lynch, Holly
Format Journal Article
LanguageEnglish
Published England Blackwell Publishing Ltd 01.10.2020
Subjects
Online AccessGet full text
ISSN0269-9702
1467-8519
1467-8519
DOI10.1111/bioe.12704

Cover

More Information
Summary:The right to withdraw from research without penalty is well established around the world. However, it has been challenged in some corners of bioethics based on concerns about various harms—to participants, to scientific integrity, and to research bystanders—that may stem from withdrawal. These concerns have become particularly salient in emerging debates about the ethics of controlled human infection (CHI) studies in which participants are intentionally infected with pathogens, often in inpatient settings with extensive follow‐up. In this article, I provide support for preserving the right to withdraw from research without penalty and demonstrate that it is also typically justified in the specific context of CHI studies. The right is well aligned with individual freedoms outside the research setting, where autonomous individuals are permitted to engage in behaviors that will foreseeably cause them harm; where they cannot be compelled to satisfy contracts for their services, nor penalized for failure to do so; and where their behavior is not constrained by public health authorities except in extreme circumstances. These freedoms are supported by U.S. law, as well as by ethical analysis that is more globally relevant. The problems associated with the right to withdraw, however, remain. The best approach to addressing them is not to restrict the right but rather to avoid initiating research when withdrawal would be especially problematic. If research proceeds, steps can still be taken to minimize participant withdrawal without infringing the right. Investigators can avoid participant surprise through informed consent focused on a study’s most burdensome aspects and promote study completion through financial incentives. Should participants nonetheless seek to withdraw, investigators may attempt to persuade them not to do so by encouraging consideration of the range of potential harms that may result. Researchers conducting CHI studies and other research from which withdrawal might be especially problematic should prepare for the possibility of participant withdrawal, respect participant requests to withdraw without penalty, and incorporate various measures to avoid such requests.
Bibliography:We would like to acknowledge the Wellcome Trust and the Brocher Foundation for facilitating a research conference on the ethics of CHI models. This work was funded by a Making a Difference Grant from the Greenwall Foundation. Wellcome Trust; Brocher Foundation; Greenwall Foundation, Grant/Award Number: Making a Difference Grant. [Correction added on 28 August 2020, after first online publication: The funding information has been updated.]
ObjectType-Article-1
SourceType-Scholarly Journals-1
ObjectType-Feature-2
content type line 14
content type line 23
ISSN:0269-9702
1467-8519
1467-8519
DOI:10.1111/bioe.12704